How Much Is Too Much?
Abstract
Ingrid Robeyns’ concept of limitarianism asks a radical but timely question: how much wealth is too much? This essay explores the moral and political case for setting limits on individual accumulation, reframing debates around inequality by focusing less on poverty and more on excess.
When we talk about injustice, our attention almost always moves downward. Poverty is the problem; deprivation is the scandal. But what if we flipped the lens and asked whether excessive wealth itself is also unjust? This is the provocation at the heart of Ingrid Robeyns’ theory of limitarianism, which argues that there should be a moral and political upper limit to personal wealth. At first, the idea sounds almost taboo. We are conditioned—especially in capitalist societies—to celebrate accumulation, to treat billionaires as aspirational figures or engines of innovation. Limitarianism interrupts this narrative by insisting that beyond a certain point, wealth becomes not just unnecessary, but morally problematic.
Robeyns’ position is deceptively simple. Once someone has secured enough resources to live a flourishing life—food, shelter, healthcare, education, opportunities for leisure and development—what justification remains for further accumulation? Every additional dollar beyond that threshold is a dollar that could have addressed urgent collective needs: climate adaptation, pandemic preparedness, or basic infrastructure for billions who still lack it. In this sense, limitarianism doesn’t present wealth as a private trophy, but as a social resource that comes with obligations.
Reading this in the shadow of libertarian theories I once studied, I can’t help but notice the contrast. For thinkers like Robert Nozick, property rights are near-sacred; freedom is defined by the absence of interference. The role of the state is to protect individuals from force or fraud and otherwise leave them alone. It’s an elegant blueprint that seems to sanctify autonomy, but the more I encounter it in practice, the more it reveals its fragility. Libertarianism tells us we have the right to be left alone, but it leaves unanswered how freedom can be meaningful if vast inequalities dictate who actually has choices and who doesn’t. It defends wealth as if it were insulated from its social consequences, as though one person’s hoarded billions do not limit another’s access to housing, clean air, or healthcare.
Limitarianism, by contrast, starts from a recognition of interdependence. Wealth doesn’t exist in a vacuum—it is made possible by institutions, social cooperation, and natural resources that no one individual created. To place limits on accumulation, then, is not to punish ambition but to acknowledge the shared foundations that make private success possible in the first place. It is also to recognize the political dangers of extreme concentration. We live in an era where the ultra-rich shape elections, fund think tanks, and set the agenda for global problems through their foundations and corporations. A democracy distorted by billionaire influence is no longer a democracy in any meaningful sense.
Still, limitarianism is not without problems. Where should the line be drawn? Who decides what counts as “enough”? Critics argue that setting an arbitrary ceiling could discourage innovation or drive wealth offshore. Even sympathetic voices worry that focusing on capping the top distracts from raising the bottom. There is truth to these concerns: it is easier to measure poverty than excess, and easier to mobilize sympathy for deprivation than to mobilize political will against luxury. Yet these objections do not erase the force of Robeyns’ challenge. If poverty is a moral scandal, why is excess not treated with equal urgency?
What I find most compelling about limitarianism is that it re-centers the ethical question. Instead of asking only how to alleviate poverty, it asks whether unlimited accumulation itself is defensible. It reframes justice not simply as lifting the floor, but as lowering the ceiling. This makes many people uncomfortable because it exposes how deeply we have naturalized inequality, how much we see billionaires as inevitable rather than as the outcome of specific policies and structures that could, in principle, be different.
For me, limitarianism resonates because it resists the neat abstractions that once drew me to libertarian theories. Where Nozick promised the dignity of inviolable rights, I now see an alibi for indifference. Where Moore’s Open Question Argument insisted that “good” cannot be reduced to natural properties, limitarianism insists that “enough” cannot be reduced to individual preference. Both gestures expose the limits of semantics when confronted with lived injustice. Philosophical neatness is seductive, but it often buckles under the weight of reality.
To take limitarianism seriously is not to settle on a number—it is to accept the principle that extreme wealth is not a private matter but a public problem. It is to recognize that in a world of climate breakdown, pandemics, and deepening inequality, the question “how much is too much?” is not just open, but urgent. And perhaps that is the value of limitarianism: not as a final doctrine, but as a refusal to let us celebrate accumulation without confronting its costs.